BasicsFunctional Programming
(* $Date: 2012-07-21 13:38:33 -0400 (Sat, 21 Jul 2012) $ *)
Enumerated Types
Days of the Week
Inductive day : Type :=
| monday : day
| tuesday : day
| wednesday : day
| thursday : day
| friday : day
| saturday : day
| sunday : day.
Having defined day, we can write functions that operate on
days.
Definition next_weekday (d:day) : day :=
match d with
| monday => tuesday
| tuesday => wednesday
| wednesday => thursday
| thursday => friday
| friday => monday
| saturday => monday
| sunday => monday
end.
One thing to note is that the argument and return types of
this function are explicitly declared. Like most functional
programming languages, Coq can often work out these types even if
they are not given explicitly — i.e., it performs some type
inference — but we'll always include them to make reading
easier.
Having defined a function, we should check that it works on
some examples. There are actually three different ways to do this
in Coq. First, we can use the command Eval simpl to evaluate a
compound expression involving next_weekday.
Eval simpl in (next_weekday friday).
(* ==> monday : day *)
Eval simpl in (next_weekday (next_weekday saturday)).
(* ==> tuesday : day *)
If you have a computer handy, now would be an excellent
moment to fire up the Coq interpreter under your favorite IDE —
either CoqIde or Proof General — and try this for yourself. Load
this file (Basics.v) from the book's accompanying Coq sources,
find the above example, submit it to Coq, and observe the
result.
The keyword simpl ("simplify") tells Coq precisely how to
evaluate the expression we give it. For the moment, simpl is
the only one we'll need; later on we'll see some alternatives that
are sometimes useful.
Second, we can record what we expect the result to be in
the form of a Coq example:
Example test_next_weekday:
(next_weekday (next_weekday saturday)) = tuesday.
This declaration does two things: it makes an
assertion (that the second weekday after saturday is tuesday),
and it gives the assertion a name that can be used to refer to it
later. Having made the assertion, we can also ask Coq to verify it,
like this:
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
The details are not important for now (we'll come back to
them in a bit), but essentially this can be read as "The assertion
we've just made can be proved by observing that both sides of the
equality are the same after simplification."
Third, we can ask Coq to "extract," from a Definition, a
program in some other, more conventional, programming
language (OCaml, Scheme, or Haskell) with a high-performance
compiler. This facility is very interesting, since it gives us a
way to construct fully certified programs in mainstream
languages. Indeed, this is one of the main uses for which Coq was
developed. We won't have space to dig further into this topic,
but more information can be found in the Coq'Art book by Bertot
and Castéran, as well as the Coq reference manual.
Inductive bool : Type :=
| true : bool
| false : bool.
Although we are rolling our own booleans here for the sake
of building up everything from scratch, Coq does, of course,
provide a default implementation of the booleans in its standard
library, together with a multitude of useful functions and
lemmas. (Take a look at Coq.Init.Datatypes in the Coq library
documentation if you're interested.) Whenever possible, we'll
name our own definitions and theorems so that they exactly
coincide with the ones in the standard library.
Functions over booleans can be defined in the same way as
above:
Definition negb (b:bool) : bool :=
match b with
| true => false
| false => true
end.
Definition andb (b1:bool) (b2:bool) : bool :=
match b1 with
| true => b2
| false => false
end.
Definition orb (b1:bool) (b2:bool) : bool :=
match b1 with
| true => true
| false => b2
end.
The last two illustrate the syntax for multi-argument
function definitions.
The following four "unit tests" constitute a complete
specification — a truth table — for the orb function:
Example test_orb1: (orb true false) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_orb2: (orb false false) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_orb3: (orb false true) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_orb4: (orb true true) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
A note on notation: We use square brackets to delimit
fragments of Coq code in comments in .v files; this convention,
also used by the coqdoc documentation tool, keeps them visually
separate from the surrounding text. In the html version of the
files, these pieces of text appear in a different font.
The following bit of Coq hackery defines a magic value
called admit that can fill a hole in an incomplete definition or
proof. We'll use it in the definition of nandb in the following
exercise. In general, your job in the exercises is to replace
admit or Admitted with real definitions or proofs.
Definition admit {T: Type} : T. Admitted.
Exercise: 1 star (nandb)
Complete the definition of the following function, then make sure that the Example assertions below each can be verified by Coq.Definition nandb (b1:bool) (b2:bool) : bool :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Remove "Admitted." and fill in each proof with
"Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed."
Example test_nandb1: (nandb true false) = true.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_nandb2: (nandb false false) = true.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_nandb3: (nandb false true) = true.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_nandb4: (nandb true true) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Definition andb3 (b1:bool) (b2:bool) (b3:bool) : bool :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Example test_andb31: (andb3 true true true) = true.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_andb32: (andb3 false true true) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_andb33: (andb3 true false true) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_andb34: (andb3 true true false) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Example test_andb31: (andb3 true true true) = true.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_andb32: (andb3 false true true) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_andb33: (andb3 true false true) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_andb34: (andb3 true true false) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Function Types
Check true.
(* ===> true : bool *)
Check (negb true).
(* ===> negb true : bool *)
Functions like negb itself are also data values, just like
true and false. Their types are called function types, and
they are written with arrows.
Check negb.
(* ===> negb : bool -> bool *)
The type of negb, written bool → bool and pronounced
"bool arrow bool," can be read, "Given an input of type
bool, this function produces an output of type bool."
Similarly, the type of andb, written bool → bool → bool, can
be read, "Given two inputs, both of type bool, this function
produces an output of type bool."
Numbers
Module Playground1.
The types we have defined so far are examples of "enumerated
types": their definitions explicitly enumerate a finite set of
elements. A more interesting way of defining a type is to give a
collection of "inductive rules" describing its elements. For
example, we can define the natural numbers as follows:
Inductive nat : Type :=
| O : nat
| S : nat → nat.
The clauses of this definition can be read:
Let's look at this in a little more detail.
Every inductively defined set (weekday, nat, bool, etc.) is
actually a set of expressions. The definition of nat says how
expressions in the set nat can be constructed:
These three conditions are the precise force of the
Inductive declaration. They imply that the expression O, the
expression S O, the expression S (S O), the expression
S (S (S O)), and so on all belong to the set nat, while other
expressions like true, andb true false, and S (S false) do
not.
We can write simple functions that pattern match on natural
numbers just as we did above — for example, predecessor:
- O is a natural number (note that this is the letter "O," not the numeral "0").
- S is a "constructor" that takes a natural number and yields another one — that is, if n is a natural number, then S n is too.
- the expression O belongs to the set nat;
- if n is an expression belonging to the set nat, then S n is also an expression belonging to the set nat; and
- expressions formed in these two ways are the only ones belonging to the set nat.
Definition pred (n : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => O
| S n' => n'
end.
The second branch can be read: "if n has the form S n'
for some n', then return n'."
End Playground1.
Definition minustwo (n : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => O
| S O => O
| S (S n') => n'
end.
Because natural numbers are such a pervasive form of data,
Coq provides a tiny bit of built-in magic for parsing and printing
them: ordinary arabic numerals can be used as an alternative to
the "unary" notation defined by the constructors S and O. Coq
prints numbers in arabic form by default:
Check (S (S (S (S O)))).
Eval simpl in (minustwo 4).
The constructor S has the type nat → nat, just like the
functions minustwo and pred:
Check S.
Check pred.
Check minustwo.
These are all things that can be applied to a number to yield a
number. However, there is a fundamental difference: functions
like pred and minustwo come with computation rules
— e.g., the definition of pred says that pred n can be
simplified to match n with | O => O | S m' => m' end — while
the definition of S has no such behavior attached. Although it
is a function in the sense that it can be applied to an argument,
it does not do anything at all!
For most function definitions over numbers, pure pattern
matching is not enough: we also need recursion. For example, to
check that a number n is even, we may need to recursively check
whether n-2 is even. To write such functions, we use the
keyword Fixpoint.
Fixpoint evenb (n:nat) : bool :=
match n with
| O => true
| S O => false
| S (S n') => evenb n'
end.
When Coq checks this definition, it notes that evenb is
"decreasing on 1st argument." What this means is that we are
performing a structural recursion over the argument n — i.e.,
that we make recursive calls only on strictly smaller values of
n. This implies that all calls to evenb will eventually
terminate. Coq demands that some argument of every Fixpoint
definition is decreasing.
We can define oddb by a similar Fixpoint declaration, but here
is a simpler definition that will be a bit easier to work with:
Definition oddb (n:nat) : bool := negb (evenb n).
Example test_oddb1: (oddb (S O)) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_oddb2: (oddb (S (S (S (S O))))) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Naturally, we can also define multi-argument functions by
recursion. (Once again, we use a module to avoid polluting the
namespace.)
Module Playground2.
Fixpoint plus (n : nat) (m : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => m
| S n' => S (plus n' m)
end.
Adding three to two now gives us five, as we'd expect.
Eval simpl in (plus (S (S (S O))) (S (S O))).
The simplification that Coq performs to reach this conclusion can
be visualized as follows:
(* plus (S (S (S O))) (S (S O))
==> S (plus (S (S O)) (S (S O))) by the second clause of the match
==> S (S (plus (S O) (S (S O)))) by the second clause of the match
==> S (S (S (plus O (S (S O))))) by the second clause of the match
==> S (S (S (S (S O)))) by the first clause of the match
*)
As a notational convenience, if two or more arguments have
the same type, they can be written together. In the following
definition, (n m : nat) means just the same as if we had written
(n : nat) (m : nat).
Fixpoint mult (n m : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => O
| S n' => plus m (mult n' m)
end.
You can match two expressions at once by putting a comma
between them:
Fixpoint minus (n m:nat) : nat :=
match n, m with
| O , _ => O
| S _ , O => n
| S n', S m' => minus n' m'
end.
The _ in the first line is a wildcard pattern. Writing _ in a
pattern is the same as writing some variable that doesn't get used
on the right-hand side. This avoids the need to invent a bogus
variable name.
End Playground2.
Fixpoint exp (base power : nat) : nat :=
match power with
| O => S O
| S p => mult base (exp base p)
end.
Example test_mult1: (mult 3 3) = 9.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Exercise: 1 star (factorial)
Recall the standard factorial function:factorial(0) = 1 factorial(n) = n * factorial(n-1) (if n>0)Translate this into Coq.
Fixpoint factorial (n:nat) : nat :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Example test_factorial1: (factorial 3) = 6.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_factorial2: (factorial 5) = (mult 10 12).
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
We can make numerical expressions a little easier to read and
write by introducing "notations" for addition, multiplication, and
subtraction.
Notation "x + y" := (plus x y)
(at level 50, left associativity)
: nat_scope.
Notation "x - y" := (minus x y)
(at level 50, left associativity)
: nat_scope.
Notation "x * y" := (mult x y)
(at level 40, left associativity)
: nat_scope.
Check ((0 + 1) + 1).
Note that these do not change the definitions we've already
made: they are simply instructions to the Coq parser to accept x
+ y in place of plus x y and, conversely, to the Coq
pretty-printer to display plus x y as x + y.
Each notation-symbol in Coq is active in a notation scope. Coq
tries to guess what scope you mean, so when you write S(O*O) it
guesses nat_scope, but when you write the cartesian
product (tuple) type bool*bool it guesses type_scope.
Occasionally you have to help it out with percent-notation by
writing (x*y)%nat, and sometimes in Coq's feedback to you it
will use %nat to indicate what scope a notation is in.
Notation scopes also apply to numeral notation (3,4,5, etc.), so you
may sometimes see 0%nat which means O, or 0%Z which means the
Integer zero.
When we say that Coq comes with nothing built-in, we really
mean it: even equality testing for numbers is a user-defined
operation! The beq_nat function tests natural numbers for equality,
yielding a boolean. Note the use of nested matches (we could
also have used a simultaneous match, as we did in minus.)
Fixpoint beq_nat (n m : nat) : bool :=
match n with
| O => match m with
| O => true
| S m' => false
end
| S n' => match m with
| O => false
| S m' => beq_nat n' m'
end
end.
Similarly, the ble_nat function tests natural numbers for
less-or-equal, yielding a boolean.
Fixpoint ble_nat (n m : nat) : bool :=
match n with
| O => true
| S n' =>
match m with
| O => false
| S m' => ble_nat n' m'
end
end.
Example test_ble_nat1: (ble_nat 2 2) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_ble_nat2: (ble_nat 2 4) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_ble_nat3: (ble_nat 4 2) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Exercise: 2 stars (blt_nat)
The blt_nat function tests natural numbers for less-than, yielding a boolean. Instead of making up a new Fixpoint for this one, define it in terms of a previously defined function.Definition blt_nat (n m : nat) : bool :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Example test_blt_nat1: (blt_nat 2 2) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_blt_nat2: (blt_nat 2 4) = true.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example test_blt_nat3: (blt_nat 4 2) = false.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Proof By Simplification
Theorem plus_O_n : ∀n:nat, 0 + n = n.
Proof.
simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
The reflexivity command implicitly simplifies both sides of the
equality before testing to see if they are the same, so we can
shorten the proof a little. (It will be useful later to know that reflexivity actually
does somwhat more than simpl — for example, it tries
"unfolding" defined terms, replacing them with their right-hand
sides. The reason for this difference is that, when reflexivity
succeeds, the whole goal is finished and we don't need to look at
whatever expanded expressions reflexivity has found; by
contrast, simpl is used in situations where we may have to read
and understand the new goal, so we would not want it blindly
expanding definitions.)
Theorem plus_O_n' : ∀n:nat, 0 + n = n.
Proof.
reflexivity. Qed.
The form of this theorem and proof are almost exactly the
same as the examples above: the only differences are that we've
added the quantifier ∀ n:nat and that we've used the
keyword Theorem instead of Example. Indeed, the latter
difference is purely a matter of style; the keywords Example and
Theorem (and a few others, including Lemma, Fact, and
Remark) mean exactly the same thing to Coq.
The keywords simpl and reflexivity are examples of tactics.
A tactic is a command that is used between Proof and Qed to
tell Coq how it should check the correctness of some claim we are
making. We will see several more tactics in the rest of this
lecture, and yet more in future lectures.
Exercise: 1 star, optional (simpl_plus)
What will Coq print in response to this query?(* Eval simpl in (forall n:nat, n + 0 = n). *)
What about this one?
(* Eval simpl in (forall n:nat, 0 + n = n). *)
Explain the difference. ☐
The intros Tactic
Theorem plus_O_n'' : ∀n:nat, 0 + n = n.
Proof.
intros n. reflexivity. Qed.
Step through this proof in Coq and notice how the goal and
context change.
Theorem plus_1_l : ∀n:nat, 1 + n = S n.
Proof.
intros n. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem mult_0_l : ∀n:nat, 0 * n = 0.
Proof.
intros n. reflexivity. Qed.
The _l suffix in the names of these theorems is
pronounced "on the left."
Theorem plus_id_example : ∀n m:nat,
n = m →
n + n = m + m.
Instead of making a completely universal claim about all numbers
n and m, this theorem talks about a more specialized property
that only holds when n = m. The arrow symbol is pronounced
"implies."
Since n and m are arbitrary numbers, we can't just use
simplification to prove this theorem. Instead, we prove it by
observing that, if we are assuming n = m, then we can replace
n with m in the goal statement and obtain an equality with the
same expression on both sides. The tactic that tells Coq to
perform this replacement is called rewrite.
Proof.
intros n m. (* move both quantifiers into the context *)
intros H. (* move the hypothesis into the context *)
rewrite → H. (* Rewrite the goal using the hypothesis *)
reflexivity. Qed.
The first line of the proof moves the universally quantified
variables n and m into the context. The second moves the
hypothesis n = m into the context and gives it the name H.
The third tells Coq to rewrite the current goal (n + n = m + m)
by replacing the left side of the equality hypothesis H with the
right side.
(The arrow symbol in the rewrite has nothing to do with
implication: it tells Coq to apply the rewrite from left to right.
To rewrite from right to left, you can use rewrite ←. Try
making this change in the above proof and see what difference it
makes in Coq's behavior.)
Exercise: 1 star (plus_id_exercise)
Remove "Admitted." and fill in the proof.Theorem plus_id_exercise : ∀n m o : nat,
n = m → m = o → n + m = m + o.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
The Admitted command tells Coq that we want to give up
trying to prove this theorem and just accept it as a given. This
can be useful for developing longer proofs, since we can state
subsidiary facts that we believe will be useful for making some
larger argument, use Admitted to accept them on faith for the
moment, and continue thinking about the larger argument until we
are sure it makes sense; then we can go back and fill in the
proofs we skipped. Be careful, though: every time you say admit
or Admitted you are leaving a door open for total nonsense to
enter Coq's nice, rigorous, formally checked world!
We can also use the rewrite tactic with a previously proved
theorem instead of a hypothesis from the context.
Theorem mult_0_plus : ∀n m : nat,
(0 + n) * m = n * m.
Proof.
intros n m.
rewrite → plus_O_n.
reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem mult_1_plus : ∀n m : nat,
(1 + n) * m = m + (n * m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(1 + n) * m = m + (n * m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Case Analysis
Theorem plus_1_neq_0_firsttry : ∀n : nat,
beq_nat (n + 1) 0 = false.
Proof.
intros n. simpl. (* does nothing! *)
Admitted.
The reason for this is that the definitions of both
beq_nat and + begin by performing a match on their first
argument. But here, the first argument to + is the unknown
number n and the argument to beq_nat is the compound
expression n + 1; neither can be simplified.
What we need is to be able to consider the possible forms of n
separately. If n is O, then we can calculate the final result
of beq_nat (n + 1) 0 and check that it is, indeed, false.
And if n = S n' for some n', then, although we don't know
exactly what number n + 1 yields, we can calculate that, at
least, it will begin with one S, and this is enough to calculate
that, again, beq_nat (n + 1) 0 will yield false.
The tactic that tells Coq to consider, separately, the cases where
n = O and where n = S n' is called destruct.
Theorem plus_1_neq_0 : ∀n : nat,
beq_nat (n + 1) 0 = false.
Proof.
intros n. destruct n as [| n'].
reflexivity.
reflexivity. Qed.
The destruct generates two subgoals, which we must then
prove, separately, in order to get Coq to accept the theorem as
proved. (No special command is needed for moving from one subgoal
to the other. When the first subgoal has been proved, it just
disappears and we are left with the other "in focus.") In this
proof, each of the subgoals is easily proved by a single use of
reflexivity.
The annotation "as [| n']" is called an "intro pattern." It
tells Coq what variable names to introduce in each subgoal. In
general, what goes between the square brackets is a list of
lists of names, separated by |. Here, the first component is
empty, since the O constructor is nullary (it doesn't carry any
data). The second component gives a single name, n', since S
is a unary constructor.
The destruct tactic can be used with any inductively defined
datatype. For example, we use it here to prove that boolean
negation is involutive — i.e., that negation is its own
inverse.
Theorem negb_involutive : ∀b : bool,
negb (negb b) = b.
Proof.
intros b. destruct b.
reflexivity.
reflexivity. Qed.
Note that the destruct here has no as clause because
none of the subcases of the destruct need to bind any variables,
so there is no need to specify any names. (We could also have
written "as [|]", or "as []".) In fact, we can omit the as
clause from any destruct and Coq will fill in variable names
automatically. Although this is convenient, it is arguably bad
style, since Coq often makes confusing choices of names when left
to its own devices.
Exercise: 1 star (zero_nbeq_plus_1)
Theorem zero_nbeq_plus_1 : ∀n : nat,
beq_nat 0 (n + 1) = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
beq_nat 0 (n + 1) = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Naming Cases
Require String. Open Scope string_scope.
Ltac move_to_top x :=
match reverse goal with
| H : _ ⊢ _ => try move x after H
end.
Tactic Notation "assert_eq" ident(x) constr(v) :=
let H := fresh in
assert (x = v) as H by reflexivity;
clear H.
Tactic Notation "Case_aux" ident(x) constr(name) :=
first [
set (x := name); move_to_top x
| assert_eq x name; move_to_top x
| fail 1 "because we are working on a different case" ].
Tactic Notation "Case" constr(name) := Case_aux Case name.
Tactic Notation "SCase" constr(name) := Case_aux SCase name.
Tactic Notation "SSCase" constr(name) := Case_aux SSCase name.
Tactic Notation "SSSCase" constr(name) := Case_aux SSSCase name.
Tactic Notation "SSSSCase" constr(name) := Case_aux SSSSCase name.
Tactic Notation "SSSSSCase" constr(name) := Case_aux SSSSSCase name.
Tactic Notation "SSSSSSCase" constr(name) := Case_aux SSSSSSCase name.
Tactic Notation "SSSSSSSCase" constr(name) := Case_aux SSSSSSSCase name.
Here's an example of how Case is used. Step through the
following proof and observe how the context changes.
Theorem andb_true_elim1 : ∀b c : bool,
andb b c = true → b = true.
Proof.
intros b c H.
destruct b.
Case "b = true".
reflexivity.
Case "b = false".
rewrite ← H. reflexivity. Qed.
Case does something very trivial: It simply adds a string
that we choose (tagged with the identifier "Case") to the context
for the current goal. When subgoals are generated, this string is
carried over into their contexts. When the last of these subgoals
is finally proved and the next top-level goal (a sibling of the
current one) becomes active, this string will no longer appear in
the context and we will be able to see that the case where we
introduced it is complete. Also, as a sanity check, if we try to
execute a new Case tactic while the string left by the previous
one is still in the context, we get a nice clear error message.
For nested case analyses (i.e., when we want to use a destruct
to solve a goal that has itself been generated by a destruct),
there is an SCase ("subcase") tactic.
Exercise: 2 stars (andb_true_elim2)
Prove andb_true_elim2, marking cases (and subcases) when you use destruct.Theorem andb_true_elim2 : ∀b c : bool,
andb b c = true → c = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
There are no hard and fast rules for how proofs should be
formatted in Coq — in particular, where lines should be broken
and how sections of the proof should be indented to indicate their
nested structure. However, if the places where multiple subgoals
are generated are marked with explicit Case tactics placed at
the beginning of lines, then the proof will be readable almost no
matter what choices are made about other aspects of layout.
This is a good place to mention one other piece of (possibly
obvious) advice about line lengths. Beginning Coq users sometimes
tend to the extremes, either writing each tactic on its own line
or entire proofs on one line. Good style lies somewhere in the
middle. In particular, one reasonable convention is to limit
yourself to 80-character lines. Lines longer than this are hard
to read and can be inconvenient to display and print. Many
editors have features that help enforce this.
Induction
Theorem plus_0_r_firsttry : ∀n:nat,
n + 0 = n.
... cannot be proved in the same simple way. Just applying
reflexivity doesn't work: the n in n + 0 is an arbitrary
unknown number, so the match in the definition of + can't be
simplified. And reasoning by cases using destruct n doesn't get
us much further: the branch of the case analysis where we assume n
= 0 goes through, but in the branch where n = S n' for some n'
we get stuck in exactly the same way. We could use destruct n' to
get one step further, but since n can be arbitrarily large, if we
try to keep on going this way we'll never be done.
Proof.
intros n.
simpl. (* Does nothing! *)
Admitted.
Case analysis gets us a little further, but not all the way:
Theorem plus_0_r_secondtry : ∀n:nat,
n + 0 = n.
Proof.
intros n. destruct n as [| n'].
Case "n = 0".
reflexivity. (* so far so good... *)
Case "n = S n'".
simpl. (* ...but here we are stuck again *)
Admitted.
To prove such facts — indeed, to prove most interesting
facts about numbers, lists, and other inductively defined sets —
we need a more powerful reasoning principle: induction.
Recall (from high school) the principle of induction over natural
numbers: If P(n) is some proposition involving a natural number
n and we want to show that P holds for all numbers n, we can
reason like this:
In Coq, the steps are the same but the order is backwards: we
begin with the goal of proving P(n) for all n and break it
down (by applying the induction tactic) into two separate
subgoals: first showing P(O) and then showing P(n') → P(S
n'). Here's how this works for the theorem we are trying to
prove at the moment:
- show that P(O) holds;
- show that, for any n', if P(n') holds, then so does P(S n');
- conclude that P(n) holds for all n.
Theorem plus_0_r : ∀n:nat, n + 0 = n.
Proof.
intros n. induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = 0". reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'". simpl. rewrite → IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
Like destruct, the induction tactic takes an as...
clause that specifies the names of the variables to be introduced
in the subgoals. In the first branch, n is replaced by 0 and
the goal becomes 0 + 0 = 0, which follows by simplification. In
the second, n is replaced by S n' and the assumption n' + 0 =
n' is added to the context (with the name IHn', i.e., the
Induction Hypothesis for n'). The goal in this case becomes (S
n') + 0 = S n', which simplifies to S (n' + 0) = S n', which in
turn follows from the induction hypothesis.
Theorem minus_diag : ∀n,
minus n n = 0.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n. induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = 0".
simpl. reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'".
simpl. rewrite → IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem mult_0_r : ∀n:nat,
n * 0 = 0.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_n_Sm : ∀n m : nat,
S (n + m) = n + (S m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_comm : ∀n m : nat,
n + m = m + n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
n * 0 = 0.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_n_Sm : ∀n m : nat,
S (n + m) = n + (S m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_comm : ∀n m : nat,
n + m = m + n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Fixpoint double (n:nat) :=
match n with
| O => O
| S n' => S (S (double n'))
end.
Lemma double_plus : ∀n, double n = n + n .
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 1 star (destruct_induction)
Briefly explain the difference between the tactics destruct and induction.Formal vs. Informal Proof
Theorem plus_assoc' : ∀n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
Proof. intros n m p. induction n as [| n']. reflexivity.
simpl. rewrite → IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
Coq is perfectly happy with this as a proof. For a human,
however, it is difficult to make much sense of it. If you're used
to Coq you can probably step through the tactics one after the
other in your mind and imagine the state of the context and goal
stack at each point, but if the proof were even a little bit more
complicated this would be next to impossible. Instead, a
mathematician mighty write it like this:
The overall form of the proof is basically similar. This is
no accident, of course: Coq has been designed so that its
induction tactic generates the same sub-goals, in the same
order, as the bullet points that a mathematician would write. But
there are significant differences of detail: the formal proof is
much more explicit in some ways (e.g., the use of reflexivity)
but much less explicit in others; in particular, the "proof state"
at any given point in the Coq proof is completely implicit,
whereas the informal proof reminds the reader several times where
things stand.
Here is a formal proof that shows the structure more
clearly:
- Theorem: For any n, m and p,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.Proof: By induction on n.
- First, suppose n = 0. We must show
0 + (m + p) = (0 + m) + p.This follows directly from the definition of +.
- Next, suppose n = S n', where
n' + (m + p) = (n' + m) + p.We must show(S n') + (m + p) = ((S n') + m) + p.By the definition of +, this follows fromS (n' + (m + p)) = S ((n' + m) + p),which is immediate from the induction hypothesis. ☐
- First, suppose n = 0. We must show
Theorem plus_assoc : ∀n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
Proof.
intros n m p. induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = 0".
reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'".
simpl. rewrite → IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
Exercise: 2 stars (plus_comm_informal)
Translate your solution for plus_comm into an informal proof.☐
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (beq_nat_refl_informal)
Write an informal proof of the following theorem, using the informal proof of plus_assoc as a model. Don't just paraphrase the Coq tactics into English!☐
Exercise: 1 star, optional (beq_nat_refl)
Theorem beq_nat_refl : ∀n : nat,
true = beq_nat n n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
true = beq_nat n n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Proofs Within Proofs
Theorem mult_0_plus' : ∀n m : nat,
(0 + n) * m = n * m.
Proof.
intros n m.
assert (H: 0 + n = n).
Case "Proof of assertion". reflexivity.
rewrite → H.
reflexivity. Qed.
The assert tactic introduces two sub-goals. The first is
the assertion itself; by prefixing it with H: we name the
assertion H. (Note that we could also name the assertion with
as just as we did above with destruct and induction, i.e.,
assert (0 + n = n) as H. Also note that we mark the proof of
this assertion with a Case, both for readability and so that,
when using Coq interactively, we can see when we're finished
proving the assertion by observing when the "Proof of assertion"
string disappears from the context.) The second goal is the same
as the one at the point where we invoke assert, except that, in
the context, we have the assumption H that 0 + n = n. That
is, assert generates one subgoal where we must prove the
asserted fact and a second subgoal where we can use the asserted
fact to make progress on whatever we were trying to prove in the
first place.
Actually, assert will turn out to be handy in many sorts of
situations. For example, suppose we want to prove that (n + m)
+ (p + q) = (m + n) + (p + q). The only difference between the
two sides of the = is that the arguments m and n to the
first inner + are swapped, so it seems we should be able to
use the commutativity of addition (plus_comm) to rewrite one
into the other. However, the rewrite tactic is a little stupid
about where it applies the rewrite. There are three uses of
+ here, and it turns out that doing rewrite → plus_comm
will affect only the outer one.
Theorem plus_rearrange_firsttry : ∀n m p q : nat,
(n + m) + (p + q) = (m + n) + (p + q).
Proof.
intros n m p q.
(* We just need to swap (n + m) for (m + n)...
it seems like plus_comm should do the trick! *)
rewrite → plus_comm.
(* Doesn't work...Coq rewrote the wrong plus! *)
Admitted.
To get plus_comm to apply at the point where we want it, we can
introduce a local lemma stating that n + m = m + n (for
the particular m and n that we are talking about here), prove
this lemma using plus_comm, and then use this lemma to do the
desired rewrite.
Theorem plus_rearrange : ∀n m p q : nat,
(n + m) + (p + q) = (m + n) + (p + q).
Proof.
intros n m p q.
assert (H: n + m = m + n).
Case "Proof of assertion".
rewrite → plus_comm. reflexivity.
rewrite → H. reflexivity. Qed.
Exercise: 4 stars, recommended (mult_comm)
Use assert to help prove this theorem. You shouldn't need to use induction.Theorem plus_swap : ∀n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = m + (n + p).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Now prove commutativity of multiplication. (You will probably
need to define and prove a separate subsidiary theorem to be used
in the proof of this one.) You may find that plus_swap comes in
handy.
Theorem mult_comm : ∀m n : nat,
m * n = n * m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem evenb_n__oddb_Sn : ∀n : nat,
evenb n = negb (evenb (S n)).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
evenb n = negb (evenb (S n)).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
More Exercises
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (more_exercises)
Take a piece of paper. For each of the following theorems, first think about whether (a) it can be proved using only simplification and rewriting, (b) it also requires case analysis (destruct), or (c) it also requires induction. Write down your prediction. Then fill in the proof. (There is no need to turn in your piece of paper; this is just to encourage you to reflect before hacking!)Theorem ble_nat_refl : ∀n:nat,
true = ble_nat n n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem zero_nbeq_S : ∀n:nat,
beq_nat 0 (S n) = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem andb_false_r : ∀b : bool,
andb b false = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_ble_compat_l : ∀n m p : nat,
ble_nat n m = true → ble_nat (p + n) (p + m) = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem S_nbeq_0 : ∀n:nat,
beq_nat (S n) 0 = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem mult_1_l : ∀n:nat, 1 * n = n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem all3_spec : ∀b c : bool,
orb
(andb b c)
(orb (negb b)
(negb c))
= true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem mult_plus_distr_r : ∀n m p : nat,
(n + m) * p = (n * p) + (m * p).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem mult_assoc : ∀n m p : nat,
n * (m * p) = (n * m) * p.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Use the replace tactic to do a proof of plus_swap', just like
plus_swap but without needing assert (n + m = m + n).
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (plus_swap')
The replace tactic allows you to specify a particular subterm to rewrite and what you want it rewritten to. More precisely, replace (t) with (u) replaces (all copies of) expression t in the goal by expression u, and generates t = u as an additional subgoal. This is often useful when a plain rewrite acts on the wrong part of the goal.Theorem plus_swap' : ∀n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = m + (n + p).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem bool_fn_applied_thrice :
∀(f : bool → bool) (b : bool),
f (f (f b)) = f b.
Proof.
intros f b.
destruct b.
Case "b = true".
remember (f true) as ftrue.
destruct ftrue.
SCase "f true = true".
rewrite ← Heqftrue.
symmetry.
apply Heqftrue.
SCase "f true = false".
remember (f false) as ffalse.
destruct ffalse.
SSCase "f false = true".
symmetry.
apply Heqftrue.
SSCase "f false = false".
symmetry.
apply Heqffalse.
remember (f false) as ffalse.
destruct ffalse.
SCase "f false = true".
remember (f true) as ftrue.
destruct ftrue.
SSCase "f true = true".
symmetry.
apply Heqftrue.
SSCase "f true = false".
symmetry.
apply Heqffalse.
SCase "f false = false".
rewrite ← Heqffalse.
symmetry.
apply Heqffalse.
Qed.
∀(f : bool → bool) (b : bool),
f (f (f b)) = f b.
Proof.
intros f b.
destruct b.
Case "b = true".
remember (f true) as ftrue.
destruct ftrue.
SCase "f true = true".
rewrite ← Heqftrue.
symmetry.
apply Heqftrue.
SCase "f true = false".
remember (f false) as ffalse.
destruct ffalse.
SSCase "f false = true".
symmetry.
apply Heqftrue.
SSCase "f false = false".
symmetry.
apply Heqffalse.
remember (f false) as ffalse.
destruct ffalse.
SCase "f false = true".
remember (f true) as ftrue.
destruct ftrue.
SSCase "f true = true".
symmetry.
apply Heqftrue.
SSCase "f true = false".
symmetry.
apply Heqffalse.
SCase "f false = false".
rewrite ← Heqffalse.
symmetry.
apply Heqffalse.
Qed.
☐
(a) First, write an inductive definition of the type bin
corresponding to this description of binary numbers.
(Hint: recall that the definition of nat from class,
(b) Next, write an increment function for binary numbers, and a
function to convert binary numbers to unary numbers.
(c) Finally, prove that your increment and binary-to-unary
functions commute: that is, incrementing a binary number and
then converting it to unary yields the same result as first
converting it to unary and then incrementing.
Exercise: 4 stars, recommended (binary)
Consider a different, more efficient representation of natural numbers using a binary rather than unary system. That is, instead of saying that each natural number is either zero or the successor of a natural number, we can say that each binary number is either- zero,
- twice a binary number, or
- one more than twice a binary number.
Inductive nat : Type :=
| O : nat
| S : nat → nat.
says nothing about what O and S "mean". It just says "O is
a nat (whatever that is), and if n is a nat then so is S n".
The interpretation of O as zero and S as successor/plus one
comes from the way that we use nat values, by writing functions to
do things with them, proving things about them, and so on. Your
definition of bin should be correspondingly simple; it is the
functions you will write next that will give it mathematical
meaning.)
| O : nat
| S : nat → nat.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
(a) First, write a function to convert natural numbers to binary
numbers. Then prove that starting with any natural number,
converting to binary, then converting back yields the same
natural number you started with.
(b) You might naturally think that we should also prove the
opposite direction: that starting with a binary number,
converting to a natural, and then back to binary yields the
same number we started with. However, it is not true!
Explain what the problem is.
(c) Define a function normalize from binary numbers to binary
numbers such that for any binary number b, converting to a
natural and then back to binary yields (normalize b). Prove
it.
Exercise: 5 stars (binary_inverse)
This exercise is a continuation of the previous exercise about binary numbers. You will need your definitions and theorems from the previous exercise to complete this one.(* FILL IN HERE *)
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (decreasing)
The requirement that some argument to each function be "decreasing" is a fundamental feature of Coq's design: In particular, it guarantees that every function that can be defined in Coq will terminate on all inputs. However, because Coq's "decreasing analysis" is not very sophisticated, it is sometimes necessary to write functions in slightly unnatural ways.(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐