PropPropositions and Evidence
(* $Date: 2012-07-23 16:26:25 -0400 (Mon, 23 Jul 2012) $ *)
Require Export Poly.
In previous chapters, we have seen many examples of factual
claims (propositions) and ways of presenting evidence of their
truth (proofs). In particular, we have worked extensively with
equality propositions of the form e1 = e2, with
implications (P → Q), and with quantified propositions
(∀ x, P).
In this chapter we take a deeper look at the way propositions are
expressed in Coq and at the structure of the logical evidence that
we construct when we carry out proofs.
Some of the concepts in this chapter may seem a bit abstract on a
first encounter. We've included a lot of exercises, most of
which should be quite approachable even if you're still working on
understanding the details of the text. Try to work as many of
them as you can, especially the one-starred exercises.
Inductively Defined Propositions
- Rule b_0: The number 0 is beautiful.
- Rule b_3: The number 3 is beautiful.
- Rule b_5: The number 5 is beautiful.
- Rule b_sum: If n and m are both beautiful, then so is their sum.
(b_0) | |
beautiful 0 |
(b_3) | |
beautiful 3 |
(b_5) | |
beautiful 5 |
beautiful n beautiful m | (b_sum) |
beautiful (n+m) |
----------- (b_3) ----------- (b_5)
beautiful 3 beautiful 5
------------------------------- (b_sum)
beautiful 8
Of course, there are other ways of using these rules to argue that
8 is beautiful — for instance:
beautiful 3 beautiful 5
------------------------------- (b_sum)
beautiful 8
----------- (b_5) ----------- (b_3)
beautiful 5 beautiful 3
------------------------------- (b_sum)
beautiful 8
beautiful 5 beautiful 3
------------------------------- (b_sum)
beautiful 8
Exercise: 1 star (varieties_of_beauty)
How many different ways are there to show that 8 is beautiful?(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
In Coq, we can express the definition of beautiful as
follows:
Inductive beautiful : nat → Prop :=
b_0 : beautiful 0
| b_3 : beautiful 3
| b_5 : beautiful 5
| b_sum : ∀n m, beautiful n → beautiful m → beautiful (n+m).
The first line declares that beautiful is a proposition — or,
more formally, a family of propositions "indexed by" natural
numbers. (For each number n, the claim that "n is
beautiful" is a proposition.) Such a family of propositions is
often called a property of numbers.
Each of the remaining lines embodies one of the rules for
beautiful numbers.
We can use Coq's tactic scripting facility to assemble proofs that
particular numbers are beautiful.
Theorem three_is_beautiful: beautiful 3.
Proof.
(* This simply follows from the axiom b_3. *)
apply b_3.
Qed.
Theorem eight_is_beautiful: beautiful 8.
Proof.
(* First we use the rule b_sum, telling Coq how to
instantiate n and m. *)
apply b_sum with (n:=3) (m:=5).
(* To solve the subgoals generated by b_sum, we must provide
evidence of beautiful 3 and beautiful 5. Fortunately we
have axioms for both. *)
apply b_3.
apply b_5.
Qed.
Proof Objects
propositions ~ types evidence ~ dataMany useful things follow from this connection. To begin with, it gives us a natural interpretation of the b_sum constructor:
b_sum : ∀ n m,
beautiful n → beautiful m → beautiful (n+m).
If we read : as "has type," this says that b_sum is a data
constructor that takes four arguments: two numbers, n and m,
and two values of type beautiful n and beautiful m. That is,
b_sum can be viewed as a function that, given evidence for the
propositions beautiful n and beautiful m, gives us evidence
for the proposition that beautiful (n+m).
beautiful n → beautiful m → beautiful (n+m).
Check (b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5).
The expression b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5 can be thought of as
instantiating the parameterized constructor b_sum with the
specific arguments 3 5 and the corresponding proof objects for
its premises beautiful 3 and beautiful 5 (Coq is smart enough
to figure out that 3+5=8). Alternatively, we can think of b_sum
as a primitive "evidence constructor" that, when applied to two
particular numbers, wants to be further applied to evidence that
those two numbers are beautiful; its type,
[
∀ n m, beautiful n → beautiful m → beautiful (n+m),
]
expresses this functionality, in the same way that the polymorphic
type ∀ X, list X in the previous chapter expressed the fact
that the constructor nil can be thought of as a function from
types to empty lists with elements of that type.
This gives us an alternative way to write the proof that 8 is
beautiful:
Theorem eight_is_beautiful': beautiful 8.
Proof.
apply (b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5).
Qed.
Notice that we're using apply here in a new way: instead of just
supplying the name of a hypothesis or previously proved theorem
whose type matches the current goal, we are supplying an
expression that directly builds evidence with the required
type.
Proof Scripts and Proof Objects
Theorem eight_is_beautiful'': beautiful 8.
Proof.
apply b_sum with (n:=3) (m:=5).
Show Proof.
apply b_3.
Show Proof.
apply b_5.
Show Proof.
Qed.
At any given moment, Coq has constructed a term with some
"holes" (indicated by ?1, ?2, and so on), and it knows what
type of evidence is needed at each hole. In the Show Proof
output, lines of the form ?1 → beautiful n record these
requirements. (The → here has nothing to do with either
implication or function types — it is just an unfortunate choice
of concrete syntax for the output!)
Each of the holes corresponds to a subgoal, and the proof is
finished when there are no more subgoals. At this point, the
Theorem command gives a name to the evidence we've built and
stores it in the global context.
Tactic proofs are useful and convenient because they avoid
building proof trees by hand, but they are not essential: in
principle, we can always construct the required evidence by hand.
Indeed, we don't even need the Theorem command: we can use
Definition instead, to directly give a global name to a piece of
evidence.
Definition eight_is_beautiful''' : beautiful 8 :=
b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5.
All these different ways of building the proof lead to exactly the
same evidence being saved in the global environment.
Print eight_is_beautiful.
(* ===> eight_is_beautiful = b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5 : beautiful 8 *)
Print eight_is_beautiful'.
(* ===> eight_is_beautiful' = b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5 : beautiful 8 *)
Print eight_is_beautiful''.
(* ===> eight_is_beautiful'' = b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5 : beautiful 8 *)
Print eight_is_beautiful'''.
(* ===> eight_is_beautiful''' = b_sum 3 5 b_3 b_5 : beautiful 8 *)
Exercise: 1 star (six_is_beautiful)
Give a tactic proof and a proof object showing that 6 is beautiful.Theorem six_is_beautiful :
beautiful 6.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Definition six_is_beautiful' : beautiful 6 :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
☐
Exercise: 1 star (nine_is_beautiful)
Give a tactic proof and a proof object showing that 9 is beautiful.Theorem nine_is_beautiful :
beautiful 9.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Definition nine_is_beautiful' : beautiful 9 :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
☐
Implications and Functions
Theorem b_plus3: ∀n, beautiful n → beautiful (3+n).
Proof.
intros n H.
apply b_sum.
apply b_3.
apply H.
Qed.
What is the proof object corresponding to b_plus3?
We've made a notational pun between → as implication and →
as the type of functions. If we take this pun seriously, then
what we're looking for is an expression whose type is
∀ n, beautiful n → beautiful (3+n) — that is, a
function that takes two arguments (one number and a piece of
evidence) and returns a piece of evidence! Here it is:
Definition b_plus3' : ∀n, beautiful n → beautiful (3+n) :=
fun n => fun H : beautiful n =>
b_sum 3 n b_3 H.
Check b_plus3'.
(* ===> b_plus3' : forall n, beautiful n -> beautiful (3+n) *)
Recall that fun n => blah means "the function that, given n,
yields blah." Another equivalent way to write this definition is:
Definition b_plus3'' (n : nat) (H : beautiful n) : beautiful (3+n) :=
b_sum 3 n b_3 H.
Check b_plus3''.
(* ===> b_plus3'' : forall n, beautiful n -> beautiful (3+n) *)
Theorem b_times2: ∀n, beautiful n → beautiful (2*n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Definition b_times2': ∀n, beautiful n → beautiful (2*n) :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Theorem b_timesm: ∀n m, beautiful n → beautiful (m*n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Induction Over Proof Objects
Inductive gorgeous : nat → Prop :=
g_0 : gorgeous 0
| g_plus3 : ∀n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (3+n)
| g_plus5 : ∀n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (5+n).
Exercise: 1 star (gorgeous_tree)
Write out the definition of gorgeous numbers using the inference rule notation.☐
Theorem gorgeous__beautiful : ∀n,
gorgeous n → beautiful n.
Proof.
intros.
(* The argument proceeds by induction on the evidence H! *)
induction H as [|n'|n'].
Case "g_0".
apply b_0.
Case "g_plus3".
apply b_sum. apply b_3.
apply IHgorgeous.
Case "g_plus5".
apply b_sum. apply b_5. apply IHgorgeous.
Qed.
Let's see what happens if we try to prove this by induction on n
instead of induction on the evidence H.
Theorem gorgeous__beautiful_FAILED : ∀n,
gorgeous n → beautiful n.
Proof.
intros. induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = 0". apply b_0.
Case "n = S n'". (* We are stuck! *)
Admitted.
Theorem gorgeous_plus13: ∀n,
gorgeous n → gorgeous (13+n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
gorgeous n → gorgeous (13+n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Definition gorgeous_plus13_po: ∀n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (13+n):=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Theorem gorgeous_sum : ∀n m,
gorgeous n → gorgeous m → gorgeous (n + m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
gorgeous n → gorgeous m → gorgeous (n + m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem beautiful__gorgeous : ∀n, beautiful n → gorgeous n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (b_times2)
Prove the g_times2 theorem below without using gorgeous__beautiful. You might find the following helper lemma useful.Lemma helper_g_times2 : ∀x y z, x + (z + y)= z + x + y.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem g_times2: ∀n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (2*n).
Proof.
intros n H. simpl.
induction H.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Evenness
Definition even (n:nat) : Prop :=
evenb n = true.
That is, we can define "n is even" to mean "the function
evenb returns true when applied to n."
Another alternative is to define the concept of evenness directly.
Instead of going via the evenb function ("a number is even if a
certain computation yields true"), we can say what the concept
of evenness means by giving two different ways of presenting
evidence that a number is even.
Inductive ev : nat → Prop :=
| ev_0 : ev O
| ev_SS : ∀n:nat, ev n → ev (S (S n)).
This definition says that there are two ways to give
evidence that a number m is even. First, 0 is even, and
ev_0 is evidence for this. Second, if m = S (S n) for some
n and we can give evidence e that n is even, then m is
also even, and ev_SS n e is the evidence.
Exercise: 1 star (double_even)
Construct a tactic proof of the following proposition.Theorem double_even : ∀n,
ev (double n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
We have seen that the proposition "some number is even" can
be phrased in two different ways — indirectly, via a boolean
testing function evenb, or directly, by inductively describing
what constitutes evidence for evenness. These two ways of
defining evenness are about equally easy to state and work with.
Which we choose is basically a question of taste.
However, for many other properties of interest, the direct
inductive definition is preferable, since writing a testing
function may be awkward or even impossible.
One such property is beautiful. This is a perfectly sensible
definition of a set of numbers, but we cannot translate its
definition directly as a Coq Fixpoint (or translate it directly
into a recursive function in any other programming language). We
might be able to find a clever way of testing this property using
a Fixpoint (indeed, it is not too hard to find one in this
case), but in general this could require arbitrarily deep
thinking. In fact, if the property we are interested in is
uncomputable, then we cannot define it as a Fixpoint no matter
how hard we try, because Coq requires that all Fixpoints
correspond to terminating computations.
On the other hand, writing an inductive definition of what it
means to give evidence for the property beautiful is
straightforward.
Exercise: 4 stars, optional (double_even_pfobj)
Try to predict what proof object is constructed by the above tactic proof. (Before checking your answer, you'll want to strip out any uses of Case, as these will make the proof object look a bit cluttered.) ☐Discussion: Computational vs. Inductive Definitions
Inverting Evidence
Theorem ev_minus2: ∀n,
ev n → ev (pred (pred n)).
Proof.
intros n E.
destruct E as [| n' E'].
Case "E = ev_0". simpl. apply ev_0.
Case "E = ev_SS n' E'". simpl. apply E'. Qed.
Exercise: 1 star, optional (ev_minus2_n)
What happens if we try to destruct on n instead of E? ☐Exercise: 1 star, recommended (ev__even)
Here is a proof that the inductive definition of evenness implies the computational one.Theorem ev__even : ∀n,
ev n → even n.
Proof.
intros n E. induction E as [| n' E'].
Case "E = ev_0".
unfold even. reflexivity.
Case "E = ev_SS n' E'".
unfold even. apply IHE'.
Qed.
Could this proof also be carried out by induction on n instead
of E? If not, why not?
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
The induction principle for inductively defined propositions does
not follow quite the same form as that of inductively defined
sets. For now, you can take the intuitive view that induction on
evidence ev n is similar to induction on n, but restricts our
attention to only those numbers for which evidence ev n could be
generated. We'll look at the induction principle of ev in more
depth below, to explain what's really going on.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 1 star (l_fails)
The following proof attempt will not succeed.
Theorem l : ∀ n,
ev n.
Proof.
intros n. induction n.
Case "O". simpl. apply ev_0.
Case "S".
...
Briefly explain why.
ev n.
Proof.
intros n. induction n.
Case "O". simpl. apply ev_0.
Case "S".
...
☐
Exercise: 2 stars (ev_sum)
Here's another exercise requiring induction.Theorem ev_sum : ∀n m,
ev n → ev m → ev (n+m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Here's another situation where we want to analyze evidence for
evenness: proving that if n+2 is even, then n is. Our first
idea might be to use destruct for this kind of case analysis:
Theorem SSev_ev_firsttry : ∀n,
ev (S (S n)) → ev n.
Proof.
intros n E.
destruct E as [| n' E'].
(* Stuck: destruct gives us un-provable subgoal here! *)
Admitted.
In the first sub-goal, we've lost the information that n is 0.
We could have used remember, but then we still need inversion
on both cases.
Theorem SSev_ev_secondtry : ∀n,
ev (S (S n)) → ev n.
Proof.
intros n E. remember (S (S n)) as n2.
destruct E as [| n' E'].
Case "n = 0". inversion Heqn2.
Case "n = S n'". inversion Heqn2. rewrite ← H0. apply E'.
Qed.
There is a much simpler way to this: we can use inversion directly
on the inductively defined proposition ev (S (S n)).
Theorem SSev__even : ∀n,
ev (S (S n)) → ev n.
Proof.
intros n E. inversion E as [| n' E']. apply E'. Qed.
(* Print SSev__even. *)
This use of inversion may seem a bit mysterious at first.
Until now, we've only used inversion on equality
propositions, to utilize injectivity of constructors or to
discriminate between different constructors. But we see here
that inversion can also be applied to analyzing evidence
for inductively defined propositions.
Here's how inversion works in general. Suppose the name
I refers to an assumption P in the current context, where
P has been defined by an Inductive declaration. Then,
for each of the constructors of P, inversion I generates
a subgoal in which I has been replaced by the exact,
specific conditions under which this constructor could have
been used to prove P. Some of these subgoals will be
self-contradictory; inversion throws these away. The ones
that are left represent the cases that must be proved to
establish the original goal.
In this particular case, the inversion analyzed the construction
ev (S (S n)), determined that this could only have been
constructed using ev_SS, and generated a new subgoal with the
arguments of that constructor as new hypotheses. (It also
produced an auxiliary equality, which happens to be useless here.)
We'll begin exploring this more general behavior of inversion in
what follows.
Exercise: 1 star (inversion_practice)
Theorem SSSSev__even : ∀n,
ev (S (S (S (S n)))) → ev n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
ev (S (S (S (S n)))) → ev n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
The inversion tactic can also be used to derive goals by showing
the absurdity of a hypothesis.
Theorem even5_nonsense :
ev 5 → 2 + 2 = 9.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
We can generally use inversion on inductive propositions.
This illustrates that in general, we get one case for each
possible constructor. Again, we also get some auxiliary
equalities that are rewritten in the goal but not in the other
hypotheses.
Theorem ev_minus2': ∀n,
ev n → ev (pred (pred n)).
Proof.
intros n E. inversion E as [| n' E'].
Case "E = ev_0". simpl. apply ev_0.
Case "E = ev_SS n' E'". simpl. apply E'. Qed.
Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (ev_ev__ev)
Finding the appropriate thing to do induction on is a bit tricky here:Theorem ev_ev__ev : ∀n m,
ev (n+m) → ev n → ev m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (ev_plus_plus)
Here's an exercise that just requires applying existing lemmas. No induction or even case analysis is needed, but some of the rewriting may be tedious. You'll want the replace tactic used for plus_swap' in Basics.vTheorem ev_plus_plus : ∀n m p,
ev (n+m) → ev (n+p) → ev (m+p).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Programming with Propositions
Check (2 + 2 = 4).
(* ===> 2 + 2 = 4 : Prop *)
Check (ble_nat 3 2 = false).
(* ===> ble_nat 3 2 = false : Prop *)
Check (beautiful 8).
(* ===> beautiful 8 : Prop *)
Both provable and unprovable claims are perfectly good
propositions. Simply being a proposition is one thing; being
provable is something else!
Check (2 + 2 = 5).
(* ===> 2 + 2 = 5 : Prop *)
Check (beautiful 4).
(* ===> beautiful 4 : Prop *)
Both 2 + 2 = 4 and 2 + 2 = 5 are legal expressions
of type Prop.
We've seen one way that propositions can be used in Coq: in
Theorem (and Lemma and Example) declarations.
Theorem plus_2_2_is_4 :
2 + 2 = 4.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
But they can be used in many other ways. For example, we
can give a name to a proposition using a Definition, just as we
have given names to expressions of other sorts (numbers,
functions, types, type functions, ...).
Definition plus_fact : Prop := 2 + 2 = 4.
Check plus_fact.
(* ===> plus_fact : Prop *)
Now we can use this name in any situation where a proposition is
expected — for example, as the claim in a Theorem
declaration.
Theorem plus_fact_is_true :
plus_fact.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
There are many ways of constructing propositions. We can define a
new proposition primitively using Inductive, we can form an
equality proposition from two computational expressions, and we
can build up a new proposition from existing ones using
implication and quantification.
Definition strange_prop1 : Prop :=
(2 + 2 = 5) → (99 + 26 = 42).
Also, given a proposition P with a free variable n, we can
form the proposition ∀ n, P.
Definition strange_prop2 :=
∀n, (ble_nat n 17 = true) → (ble_nat n 99 = true).
We can also define parameterized propositions, such as
the property of being even.
Check even.
(* ===> even : nat -> Prop *)
Check (even 4).
(* ===> even 4 : Prop *)
Check (even 3).
(* ===> even 3 : Prop *)
The type of even, nat→Prop, can be pronounced in three
equivalent ways: (1) "even is a function from numbers to
propositions," (2) "even is a family of propositions, indexed
by a number n," or (3) "even is a property of numbers."
Propositions — including parameterized propositions — are
first-class citizens in Coq. For example, we can define them to
take multiple arguments...
Definition between (n m o: nat) : Prop :=
andb (ble_nat n o) (ble_nat o m) = true.
... and then partially apply them:
Definition teen : nat→Prop := between 13 19.
We can even pass propositions — including parameterized
propositions — as arguments to functions:
Definition true_for_zero (P:nat→Prop) : Prop :=
P 0.
Here are two more examples of passing parameterized propositions
as arguments to a function. The first takes a proposition P as
argument and builds the proposition that P is true for all
natural numbers. The second takes P and builds the proposition
that, if P is true for some natural number n', then it is also
true by the successor of n' — i.e. that P is preserved by
successor:
Definition true_for_all_numbers (P:nat→Prop) : Prop :=
∀n, P n.
Definition preserved_by_S (P:nat→Prop) : Prop :=
∀n', P n' → P (S n').
Induction Principles
Induction Principles for Inductively Defined Types
Check nat_ind.
(* ===> nat_ind :
forall P : nat -> Prop,
P 0 ->
(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) ->
forall n : nat, P n *)
The induction tactic is a straightforward wrapper that, at
its core, simply performs apply t_ind. To see this more
clearly, let's experiment a little with using apply nat_ind
directly, instead of the induction tactic, to carry out some
proofs. Here, for example, is an alternate proof of a theorem
that we saw in the Basics chapter.
Theorem mult_0_r' : ∀n:nat,
n * 0 = 0.
Proof.
apply nat_ind.
Case "O". reflexivity.
Case "S". simpl. intros n IHn. rewrite → IHn.
reflexivity. Qed.
This proof is basically the same as the earlier one, but a
few minor differences are worth noting. First, in the induction
step of the proof (the "S" case), we have to do a little
bookkeeping manually (the intros) that induction does
automatically.
Second, we do not introduce n into the context before applying
nat_ind — the conclusion of nat_ind is a quantified formula,
and apply needs this conclusion to exactly match the shape of
the goal state, including the quantifier. The induction tactic
works either with a variable in the context or a quantified
variable in the goal.
Third, the apply tactic automatically chooses variable names for
us (in the second subgoal, here), whereas induction lets us
specify (with the as... clause) what names should be used. The
automatic choice is actually a little unfortunate, since it
re-uses the name n for a variable that is different from the n
in the original theorem. This is why the Case annotation is
just S — if we tried to write it out in the more explicit form
that we've been using for most proofs, we'd have to write n = S
n, which doesn't make a lot of sense! All of these conveniences
make induction nicer to use in practice than applying induction
principles like nat_ind directly. But it is important to
realize that, modulo this little bit of bookkeeping, applying
nat_ind is what we are really doing.
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (plus_one_r')
Complete this proof as we did mult_0_r' above, without using the induction tactic.Theorem plus_one_r' : ∀n:nat,
n + 1 = S n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
The induction principles that Coq generates for other datatypes
defined with Inductive follow a similar pattern. If we define a
type t with constructors c1 ... cn, Coq generates a theorem
with this shape:
t_ind :
∀ P : t → Prop,
... case for c1 ... →
... case for c2 ... →
... →
... case for cn ... →
∀ n : t, P n
The specific shape of each case depends on the arguments to the
corresponding constructor. Before trying to write down a general
rule, let's look at some more examples. First, an example where
the constructors take no arguments:
∀ P : t → Prop,
... case for c1 ... →
... case for c2 ... →
... →
... case for cn ... →
∀ n : t, P n
Inductive yesno : Type :=
| yes : yesno
| no : yesno.
Check yesno_ind.
(* ===> yesno_ind : forall P : yesno -> Prop,
P yes ->
P no ->
forall y : yesno, P y *)
Exercise: 1 star (rgb)
Write out the induction principle that Coq will generate for the following datatype. Write down your answer on paper, and then compare it with what Coq prints.Inductive rgb : Type :=
| red : rgb
| green : rgb
| blue : rgb.
Check rgb_ind.
☐
Here's another example, this time with one of the constructors
taking some arguments.
Inductive natlist : Type :=
| nnil : natlist
| ncons : nat → natlist → natlist.
Check natlist_ind.
(* ===> (modulo a little tidying)
natlist_ind :
forall P : natlist -> Prop,
P nnil ->
(forall (n : nat) (l : natlist), P l -> P (ncons n l)) ->
forall n : natlist, P n *)
Inductive natlist1 : Type :=
| nnil1 : natlist1
| nsnoc1 : natlist1 → nat → natlist1.
Now what will the induction principle look like? ☐
From these examples, we can extract this general rule:
- The type declaration gives several constructors; each corresponds to one clause of the induction principle.
- Each constructor c takes argument types a1...an.
- Each ai can be either t (the datatype we are defining) or some other type s.
- The corresponding case of the induction principle
says (in English):
- "for all values x1...xn of types a1...an, if P holds for each of the xs of type t, then P holds for c x1 ... xn".
Exercise: 1 star (ex_set)
Here is an induction principle for an inductively defined set.
ExSet_ind :
∀ P : ExSet → Prop,
(∀ b : bool, P (con1 b)) →
(∀ (n : nat) (e : ExSet), P e → P (con2 n e)) →
∀ e : ExSet, P e
Give an Inductive definition of ExSet:
∀ P : ExSet → Prop,
(∀ b : bool, P (con1 b)) →
(∀ (n : nat) (e : ExSet), P e → P (con2 n e)) →
∀ e : ExSet, P e
Inductive ExSet : Type :=
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
☐
What about polymorphic datatypes?
The inductive definition of polymorphic lists
Inductive list (X:Type) : Type :=
| nil : list X
| cons : X → list X → list X.
is very similar to that of natlist. The main difference is
that, here, the whole definition is parameterized on a set X:
that is, we are defining a family of inductive types list X,
one for each X. (Note that, wherever list appears in the body
of the declaration, it is always applied to the parameter X.)
The induction principle is likewise parameterized on X:
| nil : list X
| cons : X → list X → list X.
list_ind :
∀ (X : Type) (P : list X → Prop),
P [] →
(∀ (x : X) (l : list X), P l → P (x :: l)) →
∀ l : list X, P l
Note the wording here (and, accordingly, the form of list_ind):
The whole induction principle is parameterized on X. That is,
list_ind can be thought of as a polymorphic function that, when
applied to a type X, gives us back an induction principle
specialized to the type list X.
∀ (X : Type) (P : list X → Prop),
P [] →
(∀ (x : X) (l : list X), P l → P (x :: l)) →
∀ l : list X, P l
Exercise: 1 star (tree)
Write out the induction principle that Coq will generate for the following datatype. Compare your answer with what Coq prints.Inductive tree (X:Type) : Type :=
| leaf : X → tree X
| node : tree X → tree X → tree X.
Check tree_ind.
☐
Exercise: 1 star (mytype)
Find an inductive definition that gives rise to the following induction principle:
mytype_ind :
∀ (X : Type) (P : mytype X → Prop),
(∀ x : X, P (constr1 X x)) →
(∀ n : nat, P (constr2 X n)) →
(∀ m : mytype X, P m →
∀ n : nat, P (constr3 X m n)) →
∀ m : mytype X, P m
☐
∀ (X : Type) (P : mytype X → Prop),
(∀ x : X, P (constr1 X x)) →
(∀ n : nat, P (constr2 X n)) →
(∀ m : mytype X, P m →
∀ n : nat, P (constr3 X m n)) →
∀ m : mytype X, P m
Exercise: 1 star, optional (foo)
Find an inductive definition that gives rise to the following induction principle:
foo_ind :
∀ (X Y : Type) (P : foo X Y → Prop),
(∀ x : X, P (bar X Y x)) →
(∀ y : Y, P (baz X Y y)) →
(∀ f1 : nat → foo X Y,
(∀ n : nat, P (f1 n)) → P (quux X Y f1)) →
∀ f2 : foo X Y, P f2
☐
∀ (X Y : Type) (P : foo X Y → Prop),
(∀ x : X, P (bar X Y x)) →
(∀ y : Y, P (baz X Y y)) →
(∀ f1 : nat → foo X Y,
(∀ n : nat, P (f1 n)) → P (quux X Y f1)) →
∀ f2 : foo X Y, P f2
Exercise: 1 star, optional (foo')
Consider the following inductive definition:Inductive foo' (X:Type) : Type :=
| C1 : list X → foo' X → foo' X
| C2 : foo' X.
What induction principle will Coq generate for foo'? Fill
in the blanks, then check your answer with Coq.)
☐
foo'_ind :
∀ (X : Type) (P : foo' X → Prop),
(∀ (l : list X) (f : foo' X),
_______________________ →
_______________________ ) →
___________________________________________ →
∀ f : foo' X, ________________________
∀ (X : Type) (P : foo' X → Prop),
(∀ (l : list X) (f : foo' X),
_______________________ →
_______________________ ) →
___________________________________________ →
∀ f : foo' X, ________________________
Induction Hypotheses
∀ P : nat → Prop,
P 0 →
(∀ n : nat, P n → P (S n)) →
∀ n : nat, P n
is a generic statement that holds for all propositions
P (strictly speaking, for all families of propositions P
indexed by a number n). Each time we use this principle, we
are choosing P to be a particular expression of type
nat→Prop.
P 0 →
(∀ n : nat, P n → P (S n)) →
∀ n : nat, P n
Definition P_m0r (n:nat) : Prop :=
n * 0 = 0.
... or equivalently...
Definition P_m0r' : nat→Prop :=
fun n => n * 0 = 0.
Now when we do the proof it is easier to see where P_m0r
appears.
Theorem mult_0_r'' : ∀n:nat,
P_m0r n.
Proof.
apply nat_ind.
Case "n = O". reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'".
(* Note the proof state at this point! *)
unfold P_m0r. simpl. intros n' IHn'.
apply IHn'. Qed.
This extra naming step isn't something that we'll do in
normal proofs, but it is useful to do it explicitly for an example
or two, because it allows us to see exactly what the induction
hypothesis is. If we prove ∀ n, P_m0r n by induction on
n (using either induction or apply nat_ind), we see that the
first subgoal requires us to prove P_m0r 0 ("P holds for
zero"), while the second subgoal requires us to prove ∀ n',
P_m0r n' → P_m0r n' (S n') (that is "P holds of S n' if it
holds of n'" or, more elegantly, "P is preserved by S").
The induction hypothesis is the premise of this latter
implication — the assumption that P holds of n', which we are
allowed to use in proving that P holds for S n'.
Optional Material
Induction Principles in Prop
Inductive gorgeous : nat → Prop :=
g_0 : gorgeous 0
| g_plus3 : ∀ n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (3+m)
| g_plus5 : ∀ n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (5+m).
...to give rise to an induction principle that looks like this...
g_0 : gorgeous 0
| g_plus3 : ∀ n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (3+m)
| g_plus5 : ∀ n, gorgeous n → gorgeous (5+m).
gorgeous_ind_max :
∀ P : (∀ n : nat, gorgeous n → Prop),
P O g_0 →
(∀ (m : nat) (e : gorgeous m),
P m e → P (3+m) (g_plus3 m e) →
(∀ (m : nat) (e : gorgeous m),
P m e → P (5+m) (g_plus5 m e) →
∀ (n : nat) (e : gorgeous n), P n e
... because:
∀ P : (∀ n : nat, gorgeous n → Prop),
P O g_0 →
(∀ (m : nat) (e : gorgeous m),
P m e → P (3+m) (g_plus3 m e) →
(∀ (m : nat) (e : gorgeous m),
P m e → P (5+m) (g_plus5 m e) →
∀ (n : nat) (e : gorgeous n), P n e
- Since gorgeous is indexed by a number n (every gorgeous
object e is a piece of evidence that some particular number
n is gorgeous), the proposition P is parameterized by both
n and e — that is, the induction principle can be used to
prove assertions involving both a gorgeous number and the
evidence that it is gorgeous.
- Since there are three ways of giving evidence of gorgeousness
(gorgeous has three constructors), applying the induction
principle generates three subgoals:
- We must prove that P holds for O and b_0.
- We must prove that, whenever n is a gorgeous
number and e is an evidence of its gorgeousness,
if P holds of n and e,
then it also holds of 3+m and g_plus3 n e.
- We must prove that, whenever n is a gorgeous
number and e is an evidence of its gorgeousness,
if P holds of n and e,
then it also holds of 5+m and g_plus5 n e.
- We must prove that P holds for O and b_0.
- If these subgoals can be proved, then the induction principle tells us that P is true for all gorgeous numbers n and evidence e of their gorgeousness.
∀ P : nat → Prop,
... →
∀ n : nat, gorgeous n → P n
For this reason, Coq actually generates the following simplified
induction principle for gorgeous:
... →
∀ n : nat, gorgeous n → P n
Check gorgeous_ind.
(* ===> gorgeous_ind
: forall P : nat -> Prop,
P 0 ->
(forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> P n -> P (3 + n)) ->
(forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> P n -> P (5 + n)) ->
forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> P n *)
In particular, Coq has dropped the evidence term e as a
parameter of the the proposition P, and consequently has
rewritten the assumption ∀ (n : nat) (e: gorgeous n), ...
to be ∀ (n : nat), gorgeous n → ...; i.e., we no longer
require explicit evidence of the provability of gorgeous n.
In English, gorgeous_ind says:
We can apply gorgeous_ind directly instead of using induction.
- Suppose, P is a property of natural numbers (that is, P n is
a Prop for every n). To show that P n holds whenever n
is gorgeous, it suffices to show:
- P holds for 0,
- for any n, if n is gorgeous and P holds for
n, then P holds for 3+n,
- for any n, if n is gorgeous and P holds for n, then P holds for 5+n.
- P holds for 0,
Theorem gorgeous__beautiful' : ∀n, gorgeous n → beautiful n.
Proof.
intros.
apply gorgeous_ind.
Case "g_0".
apply b_0.
Case "g_plus3".
intros.
apply b_sum. apply b_3.
apply H1.
Case "g_plus5".
intros.
apply b_sum. apply b_5.
apply H1.
apply H.
Qed.
Module P.
Inductive p : (tree nat) → nat → Prop :=
| c1 : ∀n, p (leaf _ n) 1
| c2 : ∀t1 t2 n1 n2,
p t1 n1 → p t2 n2 → p (node _ t1 t2) (n1 + n2)
| c3 : ∀t n, p t n → p t (S n).
Describe, in English, the conditions under which the
proposition p t n is provable.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
☐
End P.
More on the induction Tactic
- If P n is some proposition involving a natural number n, and
we want to show that P holds for all numbers n, we can
reason like this:
- show that P O holds
- show that, if P n' holds, then so does P (S n')
- conclude that P n holds for all n.
Theorem plus_assoc' : ∀n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
Proof.
(* ...we first introduce all 3 variables into the context,
which amounts to saying "Consider an arbitrary n, m, and
p..." *)
intros n m p.
(* ...We now use the induction tactic to prove P n (that
is, n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p) for _all_ n,
and hence also for the particular n that is in the context
at the moment. *)
induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = O". reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'".
(* In the second subgoal generated by induction -- the
"inductive step" -- we must prove that P n' implies
P (S n') for all n'. The induction tactic
automatically introduces n' and P n' into the context
for us, leaving just P (S n') as the goal. *)
simpl. rewrite → IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
It also works to apply induction to a variable that is
quantified in the goal.
Theorem plus_comm' : ∀n m : nat,
n + m = m + n.
Proof.
induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = O". intros m. rewrite → plus_0_r. reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'". intros m. simpl. rewrite → IHn'.
rewrite ← plus_n_Sm. reflexivity. Qed.
Note that induction n leaves m still bound in the goal —
i.e., what we are proving inductively is a statement beginning
with ∀ m.
If we do induction on a variable that is quantified in the goal
after some other quantifiers, the induction tactic will
automatically introduce the variables bound by these quantifiers
into the context.
Theorem plus_comm'' : ∀n m : nat,
n + m = m + n.
Proof.
(* Let's do induction on m this time, instead of n... *)
induction m as [| m'].
Case "m = O". simpl. rewrite → plus_0_r. reflexivity.
Case "m = S m'". simpl. rewrite ← IHm'.
rewrite ← plus_n_Sm. reflexivity. Qed.
Exercise: 1 star, optional (plus_explicit_prop)
Rewrite both plus_assoc' and plus_comm' and their proofs in the same style as mult_0_r'' above — that is, for each theorem, give an explicit Definition of the proposition being proved by induction, and state the theorem and proof in terms of this defined proposition.(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
One more quick digression, for adventurous souls: if we can define
parameterized propositions using Definition, then can we also
define them using Fixpoint? Of course we can! However, this
kind of "recursive parameterization" doesn't correspond to
anything very familiar from everyday mathematics. The following
exercise gives a slightly contrived example.
Exercise: 4 stars, optional (true_upto_n__true_everywhere)
Define a recursive function true_upto_n__true_everywhere that makes true_upto_n_example work.(*
Fixpoint true_upto_n__true_everywhere
(* FILL IN HERE *)
Example true_upto_n_example :
(true_upto_n__true_everywhere 3 (fun n => even n))
= (even 3 -> even 2 -> even 1 -> forall m : nat, even m).
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
*)
☐
Building Proof Objects Incrementally
Definition b_16_atmpt_1 : beautiful 16 := admit.
Maybe we can use b_sum to construct a term of type beautiful 16?
Recall that b_sum is of type
If we can demonstrate the beauty of 5 and 11, we should
be done.
∀ n m : nat, beautiful n → beautiful m → beautiful (n + m)
Definition b_16_atmpt_2 : beautiful 16 := b_sum 5 11 admit admit.
In the attempt above, we've omitted the proofs of the propositions
that 5 and 11 are beautiful. But the first of these is already
axiomatized in b_5:
Definition b_16_atmpt_3 : beautiful 16 := b_sum 5 11 b_5 admit.
What remains is to show that 11 is beautiful. We repeat the
procedure:
Definition b_16_atmpt_4 : beautiful 16 :=
b_sum 5 11 b_5 (b_sum 5 6 admit admit).
Definition b_16_atmpt_5 : beautiful 16 :=
b_sum 5 11 b_5 (b_sum 5 6 b_5 admit).
Definition b_16_atmpt_6 : beautiful 16 :=
b_sum 5 11 b_5 (b_sum 5 6 b_5 (b_sum 3 3 admit admit)).
And finally, we can complete the proof object:
Definition b_16 : beautiful 16 :=
b_sum 5 11 b_5 (b_sum 5 6 b_5 (b_sum 3 3 b_3 b_3)).
To recap, we've been guided by an informal proof that we have in
our minds, and we check the high level details before completing
the intricacies of the proof. The admit term allows us to do
this.
Additional Exercises
Exercise: 4 stars, recommended (palindromes)
A palindrome is a sequence that reads the same backwards as forwards.- Define an inductive proposition pal on list X that
captures what it means to be a palindrome. (Hint: You'll need
three cases. Your definition should be based on the structure
of the list; just having a single constructor
c : ∀ l, l = rev l → pal lmay seem obvious, but will not work very well.)
- Prove that
∀ l, pal (l ++ rev l).
- Prove that
∀ l, pal l → l = rev l.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 5 stars, optional (palindrome_converse)
Using your definition of pal from the previous exercise, prove that
∀ l, l = rev l → pal l.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 4 stars (subsequence)
A list is a subsequence of another list if all of the elements in the first list occur in the same order in the second list, possibly with some extra elements in between. For example,
[1,2,3]
is a subsequence of each of the lists
[1,2,3]
[1,1,1,2,2,3]
[1,2,7,3]
[5,6,1,9,9,2,7,3,8]
but it is not a subsequence of any of the lists
[1,1,1,2,2,3]
[1,2,7,3]
[5,6,1,9,9,2,7,3,8]
[1,2]
[1,3]
[5,6,2,1,7,3,8]
[1,3]
[5,6,2,1,7,3,8]
- Define an inductive proposition subseq on list nat that
captures what it means to be a subsequence. (Hint: You'll need
three cases.)
- Prove that subsequence is reflexive, that is, any list is a
subsequence of itself.
- Prove that for any lists l1, l2, and l3, if l1 is a
subsequence of l2, then l1 is also a subsequence of l2 ++
l3.
- (Optional, harder) Prove that subsequence is transitive — that is, if l1 is a subsequence of l2 and l2 is a subsequence of l3, then l1 is a subsequence of l3. Hint: choose your induction carefully!
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
☐
☐
☐
☐
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (foo_ind_principle)
Suppose we make the following inductive definition:
Inductive foo (X : Set) (Y : Set) : Set :=
| foo1 : X → foo X Y
| foo2 : Y → foo X Y
| foo3 : foo X Y → foo X Y.
Fill in the blanks to complete the induction principle that will be
generated by Coq.
| foo1 : X → foo X Y
| foo2 : Y → foo X Y
| foo3 : foo X Y → foo X Y.
foo_ind
: ∀ (X Y : Set) (P : foo X Y → Prop),
(∀ x : X, __________________________________) →
(∀ y : Y, __________________________________) →
(________________________________________________) →
________________________________________________
: ∀ (X Y : Set) (P : foo X Y → Prop),
(∀ x : X, __________________________________) →
(∀ y : Y, __________________________________) →
(________________________________________________) →
________________________________________________
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (bar_ind_principle)
Consider the following induction principle:
bar_ind
: ∀ P : bar → Prop,
(∀ n : nat, P (bar1 n)) →
(∀ b : bar, P b → P (bar2 b)) →
(∀ (b : bool) (b0 : bar), P b0 → P (bar3 b b0)) →
∀ b : bar, P b
Write out the corresponding inductive set definition.
: ∀ P : bar → Prop,
(∀ n : nat, P (bar1 n)) →
(∀ b : bar, P b → P (bar2 b)) →
(∀ (b : bool) (b0 : bar), P b0 → P (bar3 b b0)) →
∀ b : bar, P b
Inductive bar : Set :=
| bar1 : ________________________________________
| bar2 : ________________________________________
| bar3 : ________________________________________.
| bar1 : ________________________________________
| bar2 : ________________________________________
| bar3 : ________________________________________.
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (no_longer_than_ind)
Given the following inductively defined proposition:
Inductive no_longer_than (X : Set) : (list X) → nat → Prop :=
| nlt_nil : ∀ n, no_longer_than X [] n
| nlt_cons : ∀ x l n, no_longer_than X l n →
no_longer_than X (x::l) (S n)
| nlt_succ : ∀ l n, no_longer_than X l n →
no_longer_than X l (S n).
write the induction principle generated by Coq.
| nlt_nil : ∀ n, no_longer_than X [] n
| nlt_cons : ∀ x l n, no_longer_than X l n →
no_longer_than X (x::l) (S n)
| nlt_succ : ∀ l n, no_longer_than X l n →
no_longer_than X l (S n).
no_longer_than_ind
: ∀ (X : Set) (P : list X → nat → Prop),
(∀ n : nat, ____________________) →
(∀ (x : X) (l : list X) (n : nat),
no_longer_than X l n → ____________________ →
_____________________________ →
(∀ (l : list X) (n : nat),
no_longer_than X l n → ____________________ →
_____________________________ →
∀ (l : list X) (n : nat), no_longer_than X l n →
____________________
: ∀ (X : Set) (P : list X → nat → Prop),
(∀ n : nat, ____________________) →
(∀ (x : X) (l : list X) (n : nat),
no_longer_than X l n → ____________________ →
_____________________________ →
(∀ (l : list X) (n : nat),
no_longer_than X l n → ____________________ →
_____________________________ →
∀ (l : list X) (n : nat), no_longer_than X l n →
____________________
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (R_provability)
Suppose we give Coq the following definition:
Inductive R : nat → list nat → Prop :=
| c1 : R 0 []
| c2 : ∀ n l, R n l → R (S n) (n :: l)
| c3 : ∀ n l, R (S n) l → R n l.
Which of the following propositions are provable?
| c1 : R 0 []
| c2 : ∀ n l, R n l → R (S n) (n :: l)
| c3 : ∀ n l, R (S n) l → R n l.
- R 2 [1,0]
- R 1 [1,2,1,0]
- R 6 [3,2,1,0]